La importancia (creciente) del liberalismo. Algunos libros.

Lista de libros (por Miguel Anxo Bastos)

  1. Mañana el capitalismo, Henri Lepage
  2. La gran ilusión, Norman Angell
  3. Libertad o igualdadKuehnelt Leddihn
  4. El milagro Europeo, Eric Jones
  5. Los orígenes del capitalismoJean Baechler
  6. Derecho legislación y libertad (vol. I, II y III), F.A. Hayek (vol. II, “El espejismo de la justicia social”)
  7. Fundamentos de la libertad, F.A. Hayek
  8. Precios y producción, F.A. Hayek
  9. El capitalismo del pentágono, Seymour Neymar
  10. El manantial, Any Rand
  11. El Estado, Anthony de Jasay
  12. Teoría e Historia, Ludwig von Mises
  13. Socialismo, cálculo económico y función empresarialJesús Huerta de Soto
  14. Auge y decadencia de las grandes potencias, Paul Kennedy
  15. Crítica del intervencionismo, Ludwig von Mises
  16. La envidia igualitaria, Gonzalo Fernández de la Mora
  17. Los errores de la nueva ciencia económica, Henry Hazlitt
  18. Teoría positiva del capital, Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk

Bonus Tracks (en construcción)

  1. La increíble maquina de hacer pan, R.W. Grant
  2. La economía en una lección, Henry Hazlitt
  3. El corazón invisible, Russ Roberts
  4. Un mundo feliz, Aldous Huxley
  5. El mundo de ayer, Stefan Zweig
  6. La miseria del historicismo, Karl Popper
  7. El cisne negro, Nassim N. Taleb
  8. La antropología del capitalismo, Rafael Termes
  9. Gobierno omnipotente, Ludwig von Mises
  10. Dinero, crédito bancario y ciclos económicos, Jesús Huerta de Soto
  11. Historia bancaria de los Estados Unidos, Murray N. Rothbard
  12. Falacias económicas, F. Bastiat
  13. Camino de servidumbre, F.A. Hayek
  14. Antifrágil, Nassim N. Taleb
  15. The Man versus the State, Herbert Spencer
  16. EnsayosMontagne
  17. Civilización, Niall Ferguson
  18. The Cash Nexus, Niall Ferguson
  19. El capital humano, Gary Becker
  20. Capitalismo y libertad, Milton Freedman
  21. Las culturas fracasadas, José Antonio Marina
  22. La fatal arrogancia: los errores del socialismo, F.A. Hayek
  23. The Nature of the Firm, Ronald Coase
  24. The Rational Optimist, Matt Ridley
  25. The Tipping Point, Malcolm Galdwell
  26. The Wisdow of the CrowdsJames Surowiecki
  27. The Commanding Heights, Daniel Yergin y Joseph Stanislaw
  28. Meditaciones, Marco Aurelio
  29. Sobre la brevedad de la vida y la felicidad, Séneca
  30. Cartas a su hijo, Lord Chesterfield
  31. La Mediterránea y los bárbaros del Norte, Luis Racionero
  32. On Human Nature, David Hume
  33. Teoría de los sentimientos morales, Adam Smith
  34. La sociedad abierta y sus enemigos, Karl Popper
  35. The Bourgeois Virtues, Dierdre N. McCloskey
  36. Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance, Douglass North
  37. The Coming of Post-Industrial Society, Daniel Bell
  38. Proceso al Estado, Lorenzo Bernaldo de Quirós
  39. The Great Escape, Angus Deaton
  40. The Tyranny of Experts, Bill Easterly
  41. Governing the Commons, Elinor Ostrom
  42. Thinking Fast and Slow, Daniel Kahneman
  43. A Conflict of Visions, Thomas Sowell
  44. The Counter-Revolution of Science, F.A. Hayek
  45. Individualism and Economic Order, F.A. Hayek
  46. Institutional Foundations of Impersonal Exchange, Benito Arruñada
  47. Adapt, Tim Harford
  48. The Liar’s Poker, Michael Lewis
  49. The Intelligent Investor, Benjamin Graham
  50. Why Nations Fail, Daron Acemoglu y James Robinson
  51. Economic Facts and Fallacies, Thomas Sowell
  52. Knowledge and Decisions, Thomas Sowell
  53. The Theory of Free Banking: Money Supply under Competitive Note Issue, George Selgin
  54. El antiguo régimen y la revolución, Alexis de Tocqueville
  55. El criterio, Jaime Balmes
  56. Reflections on the Revolution in France, Edmund Burke
  57. Good Money, George Selgin
  58. The Great Depression, Murray N. Rothbard
  59. La conquista de la pobreza, Peter T. Bauer
  60. La teoría de la eficiencia dinámica, Jesús Huerta de Soto
  61. Discovery and the Capitalist Process, Israel Kirzner
  62. Bienestar social y mecanismos de mercado, Joaquín Trigo
  63. Competition and Entrepreneurship, Israel Kirzner
  64. Discovery and the Capitalist Process, Israel Kirzner
  65. Las primeras burbujas especulativas, Douglas E. French
  66. Método de las ciencias sociales, Carl Menger
  67. Ensayos políticos, David Hume
  68. La libertad y la ley, Bruno Leoni
  69. Principios de un orden social liberal, F.A. Hayek
  70. Los enemigos del comercio, Antonio Escohotado

The Cultural and Political Consequences of Fiat Money, Jörg Guido Hülsmann (30/11/2014), Mises

 

 

 

It may seem unusual that an economist would talk about culture. Usually, we talk about prices and production, quantities produced, employment, the structure of production, scarce resources, and entrepreneurship.

But there are certain things that economists can say about the culture, and more precisely, that economists can say about the transformation of the culture. So what is culture? Well, to put it simply, it is the way we do things. This can include the way we eat — whether or not we dine with family members on a regular basis, for example — how we sleep, and how we use automobiles or other modes of transportation. And of course, the way we produce, consume, or accumulate capital are important aspects of the culture as well.

Limiting Budget Is the Key to Limiting Governments

Now to understand the effects of fiat money on the culture, we must first look at the relationship between financial systems and the nature of government.

A number of economists have observed that fiat money is a prerequisite for tyrannical government, and the idea that monetary interventionism paves the way for tyrannical government is very old and goes back to Nicolas Oresme in the fourteenth century. It has not been emphasized in the twentieth century, but Ludwig von Mises is among the few who has stressed the importance of this relationship.

Mises said that when it comes to limiting government power, it is essential that the government is financially dependent on the citizens, and this addresses the fundamental political problem of controlling the people in office once they are there. We know that generally, once they are in office, elected politicians turn around and do very different things than they said they would do, with many acting contrary to the common good and interests of their constituents.

So how do we ensure that the people in power can be controlled?

Mises tells us the way we control government is through the budget, and this is necessary in a free society. In a democratic system, at least, we elect certain people to the government, and they often enter office believing that they have a mandate to do certain types of things while in office.

But it’s not sufficient that the people tell government officials what they should be doing. It is equally important, if not more important, to dictate how much money the government will have to achieve those ends. So, it is not enough to tell the government that it will only protect private property. This mandate could be pursued with $100,000 or a billion dollars depending on what the people are willing to pay. So if the budget it not controlled, a limited mandate in itself offers no limitation on taxation or how much money is spent.

Mises believed that those who paid the taxes would then need to specifically limit the size of the government budget. The mission of the government does not by itself deter- mine the amount of resources to be used in the mission.

In response, many will complain that if budgets are tightly controlled, then we’ll never have an increase in government services because people hate taxes. That might be so, but, of course, that is the point.

Now, if we abandon a strict connection between what the citizens pay and what government spends, then we find that we move away from rule by the citizens who are being taxed, and toward greater rule by the elites.

The first way this shift can happen is by the government going into debt. The financial relationships then shift toward the new group that is funding the government, namely those who are extending credit to the government. This then weakens the relationship to the citizens who are being taxed, and it also allows the government to spend more money than would have been possible with taxation alone.

Now of course fiat money allows government to take out loans to an unlimited extent because fiat money by definition can be produced without limitation, without commercial limitation or technological limitation, and can be produced in whatever amount is desired. In this way, the government benefits from the support of a central bank, which is to be expected because the central bank itself depends on the legal framework of monopoly provided by the government.

Through these means of finding government revenues outside of directly taxing the population, we see then that fiat money allows for an extension of government activities unconnected to the willingness of the population to actually support revenue increases. In turn, the government’s rule becomes rule by elites such as central bankers and financiers rather than rule by the taxpayers, and the government’s ability to spend becomes more dependent on the ability to access fiat money than the ability to convince the citizens to accept a higher tax burden.

The Cultural Features of a Debt Economy

Now we come to the many ways through which a fiat money system affects the behavior of ordinary citizens.

One of the central features of a fiat money system is that it tends to produce near-permanent price inflation. This contrasts with the workings of an economy based on natural monies such as gold and silver. Here the price levels tend to stay flat over the long run or decline, especially in the presence of vigorous economic growth. We saw this throughout the nineteenth century in both Europe and the US, where deflationary growth has been the rule.

The reality of price inflation shapes culture in a variety of ways and much of this is deliberate, as it has long been an idea among government planners and ideologues of all sorts, even before Keynes, that ordinary people should be prevented from “hoarding” money at their homes.

In a free economy with a natural monetary system, there is a strong incentive to save money in the form of cash held under one’s immediate control. Investments in savings accounts or other relatively safe investments also play a certain role, but cash hoarding is paramount, especially among low-income families.

By contrast, when there is constant price inflation, as in a fiat-money system, cash hoarding becomes suicidal. Other financial strategies now become more advisable. It becomes advisable to exchange one’s cash for “financial products,” thus offsetting the loss of purchasing power of money through the return on that financial investment. It also becomes advisable to go into debt and leverage one’s investments. In a word, it becomes rational to pursue riskier investments in order to find a rate of return that can match or exceed the rate of price inflation. This is true across all sectors, including households and productive operations.

Before the twentieth century and widespread access to fiat money, debt was far less common and there were cultural imperatives against going into debt for consumption. Credit for households, for example, was virtually unknown before the twentieth century, and only very poor households fell back on debt to finance consumption.

But in a fiat money system, as price inflation diminishes the value of one’s monetary savings, we are encouraged to adopt a short-term perspective. That is, we need to hurry up to obtain credit as soon as possible and obtain revenue from that debt as soon as possible, because savings lose value if we just hold on to cash.

It no longer makes sense to save up money for a decade to buy a house, for example. It is much more opportune to go into debt to buy a house immediately and to pay back the loan in devalued money. There is then a generalized rush into leverage in a fiat money system since debt- financed investment brings greater returns than savings in cash or equity-financed investments.

It needs to be stressed that this tendency has no natural stopping point. In other words, fiat-money systems tend to make people insatiable in their quest for ever higher monetary returns on their investments. In a natural monetary system, as savings increase, the return on investments of all sorts diminishes. It becomes ever less interesting to invest one’s savings in order to earn a return, and thus other motivations shift into the foreground. Savings will be used increasingly to finance personal projects including the acquisition of durable consumers’ goods, but also philanthropic activity. This is exactly what we saw in the West during the nineteenth century.

By contrast, in a fiat money society, you are more likely to increase your returns by remaining in debt and continuing to chase monetary revenue indefinitely by leveraging more and more funds.

You can imagine, then, how this inflation and debt- based system, over time, will begin to change the culture of a society and its behavior.

We become more materialistic than under a natural monetary system. We can’t just sit on our savings anymore, and we have to watch our investments constantly, and think about revenue constantly, because if it is not earning enough, we are actively getting poorer.

The fact that the fiat money system pushes us into riskier investments also increases dependency on others because one must depend on the good behavior of those on whom the value of our investments depend.

Similarly, the stronger the level of debt the stronger is the selfish concern about the behavior of others who may owe us money. So fiat money creates an attempt to control others through the political system.

But at the same time, no household and no firm individually has an interest in abolishing the fiat system and putting in its place a natural monetary system. The short-term costs of such a transition would be immense. In this, we see that we are in a “rationality trap” in which one is motivated to maintain the fiat money system in spite of all its downsides, and because the culture at this point is so transformed by more than a century of easy access to fiat money.

Conclusion

We can apply economic analysis to explain cultural transformation, and a particularly important example is fiat money. It has a very important impact on our culture. This is something we would not see unless we step back and take a longer-term historical perspective. Of course, there are many other factors that come into play, but fiat money is an important factor, and the system is perpetuated by the fact that everyone stands to lose in the short run if the current system ceases to function. Moreover, given how our modern culture has been so shaped by fiat money systems, it runs against the very cultural foundations of our current society. In spite of the many short-term costs, we should nonetheless dare to change this system, and it is ultimately a question of courage, and insight, and of the will.

The morality of debt by K. Dyson (via Foreign Policy)

Credit and debt are more than just rational material exchanges within a market economy. They are socially constructed and center on matters of hard moral judgments about character, equity, and “good conscience.” These judgments are, in turn, bound up with powerful emotions of resentment, shame, and humiliation. Changing and conflicting representations of personal credit and debt deeply affect the power and welfare of states.

DEBT SLAVERY

A diversity of social meanings has been attached to debt over time. And yet certain patterns do recur. In various European languages debt co-occurs with “bondage,” “freedom,” “gratitude,” and “honor,” as in “freedom from debt,” “debt of gratitude,” and “debt of honor.”

In Dutch and German, the word Schuld means both debt and guilt. A similar linguistic association is found in the Hebrew word Chayav. These terms illustrate the deep-seated cultural anxiety attached todebt and the powerful feelings of shame it can provoke. For Germans, the fabled Swabian housewife is the traditional cultural icon of virtuous economic conduct: One should “live within one’s means.” German Chancellor Angela Merkel appropriated this icon in justifying her policies regarding the post-2010 euro area sovereign debt crises.

Reflecting his German context, Friedrich Nietzsche offered an anthropological account of the historical association of guilt with indebtedness (das Schuldgefühl). He stressed that debt was bound up with the moralization of concepts of duty, honor, self-esteem, and standing. In On the Genealogy of Morals, Nietzsche looked back to the “oldest and most primitive” personal relationship between creditor and debtor as the origin of how “one person first measured himself against another.”

Indeed, credit and debt did pre-date money. They took the form of favors among friends and neighbors, which created personal moral obligations. Later, the creation of money provided a unit of account for keeping track of debts. More importantly, it led to a de-personalization of creditor-debtor relations, making commercial society possible. This evolution was bound up with the innovation of posting and exacting collateral. In this way, debt became bound up with the threat, and often reality, of the erosion of freedom, not just for individuals but for entire families. They found themselves in a condition of “debt slavery.”

Because of the connotation of enslavement, revolutionary changes of power, or the accession of new rulers, frequently brought with them debt cancellations and destruction of debt records. The first recorded example of this appears to be in 2400 BC by King Enmetena in the Sumerian city-state of Lagash in Mesopotamia. Thereafter, the biblical proverb “The rich rules over the poor, and the borrower is servant to the lender” was used to justify the cancellation of “odious” debts after regime change. It was also used in condemnation of debtors’ prisons, for instance in the works of Charles Dickens.

From the eighteenth century onward, there were two main catalysts for rethinking notions of debt. The first was the rise of a new commercial society, which was associated with property rights and the multiplication of contractual relations, encouraged above all by the use of collateral to expand credit. Parties normally ineligible to borrow were able to enter into credit transactions. The consequence was a society in which creditor–debtor relations assumed central social and political significance, represented by an aspiring merchant-financier class, rentiers, and newly self-confident professions of accountancy and law.

The second catalyst for rethinking debt was the birth and huge increase in public debt. This transformation opened up the question of whether this development was a force for good or ill. In France, for example, the ruinous French royal finances in the eighteenth century had a profound effect on economic thinking. The French philosopher Montesquieu expressed his anxiety in The Spirit of the Laws. Public debt, he wrote, “takes the true revenue of the state from those who have activity and industry, to convey it to the indolent: that is, it gives facilities for labor to those who do not work, and clogs with difficulties those who do work.”

Meanwhile, the Scottish thinkers David Hume and Adam Smith feared that the seductions of publicdebt were corrupting states and generating a politics of illusion and hubris. Public debt financing facilitated ruinous wars in Europe and underpinned the vain pursuit of empire in the Atlantic, the Mediterranean, and India. It also enlarged political patronage, creating a mutual dependence between states and creditors that led to oligarchy and factionalism and risked the collapse of public virtue.

The debate about whether public debt promoted the virtues of commerce or the vice of profligacy was also at the heart of the acrimonious dispute between Alexander Hamilton and Thomas Jefferson in the wake of the U.S. War of Independence. In the name of virtue, Jefferson attacked Hamilton’s pursuit of public debt financing, commercial empire, and executive patronage. He argued that the priority should be to freeing the new nation of debt. In an 1809 letter to the U.S. Secretary of the Treasury Albert Gallatin, Jefferson claimed:

There does not exist an engine so corruptive of the government and so demoralizing of the nation as a public debt. It will bring on us more ruin at home than all the enemies from abroad against which this army and navy are to protect us.

From the mid-nineteenth century on, though the emerging German historical and institutional school of economics took a very different view of public debt from that of Montesquieu, Hume, Smith, and Jefferson. They were united in the view that public debt was an integral part of national economies. The thinkers Karl Dietzel and Lorenz von Stein believed that the state had a positive role to play in balancing the economy, above all by financing productivity-enhancing investment in infrastructure and public provision. Dietzel, for one, argued that, “A nation is so much the richer and its national economy so much more blossoming and progressing, the greater the ratio of interest payments on government bonds in total government outlays is.” And, for his part, Stein stressed the role of public debt as collective insurance, above all in helping provide for old age, and thus in promoting social and political integration. However, he became aware that public debt could be politically abused to finance current consumption rather than productivity-enhancing investment. Hence, Stein called for a constitutional safeguard against this misuse, a form of “golden rule” in public finances later taken up in the Basic Law of the German Federal Republic.

The belief in the usefulness of debt seemed to triumph over Montesquieu, Hume, Smith, and Jefferson’s aversions. Levels of public debt of over 100 percent of GDP were far from exceptional in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. Political economy changed profoundly as new social forces entered the political arena. Public debt grew with the radical transformation of the technology, scale, and conduct of war. New communication technologies enabled cross-nationally mobile credit. And the concentrated structure of financial markets made public balance sheets more vulnerable to big banking crises.

That vulnerability only grew with new private-sector technologies of credit creation. In addition, the secularization of society eroded attachment to inherited religious and folk beliefs about debt. It was accompanied by new belief in the scientific management of public finances, including creative financial engineering. These factors combined to facilitate the emergence of new, less constraining ideologies of debt. Gone were the days in which, intellectually, the dominant role of prudence or practical wisdom in reasoning about virtuous private and public conduct acted as an inhibition ondebt.

A key aspect of this revolution was the increasingly abstract nature of money. The German author Johann Wolfgang von Goethe gave dramatic expression to the loosening sense of guilt that was associated with the move to fiat currency. In FaustPart Two, Mephistopheles advises the Holy Roman Emperor:

Such paper, in the place of actual gold, is practical: we know just what we hold…But wise men will, when they have studied it, place infinite trust in what is infinite.

By the late twentieth century, the loosening of the sense of constraint and guilt attached to debt took a radically new form. Consumers and investors could make use of electronic money. The age of cyberfinance reshaped attitudes toward credit: “Money is now endless,” the economist Satyajit Das wrote in Extreme Money, “capable of infinite multiplication and completely unreal.” It also created a widespread sense of confusion, unease, and alarm about the implications for the behavior of banks and for how central banks managed money, for instance quantitative easing.

The implications of decline in prudence became ever more serious with the huge growth in the scale of financial assets; with the size, complexity, and opacity of the financial institutions managing these assets; and with the proliferation of ever-more exotic credit instruments, like securitization and collateralized debt obligations. Science-based models induced the illusion that credit risks were better controlled. And the ease of credit creation enabled hubris on a historically new scale.

Changes in attitudes to debt and risk were also bound up with new discourses about social entitlement. Consumer expectations of ever-higher living standards were fuelled by more lenient and readily available bank lending, the subsequent booms in construction and property market sectors, and the expansion of retail sectors, modern advertising, and marketing. Social status and identity became closely associated with consumption, in particular with the concept of luxury. Identifying oneself with the good life meant being able to live beyond traditional understandings of basic needs.Debt was the price one paid for the joys of being part of a hedonistic consumer culture. Its denial had the potential to foster a deep sense of loss, despair, social protest, and riot.

Twentieth-century discourse illustrated the profound moral ambiguities associated with debt—and the associated difficulties in framing and using state power. On the one hand, social entitlement, market society, hedonistic consumer culture, and neo-Keynesian economics suggest that the old idea of prudence had been fully dethroned. On the other hand, the notion that the state is “the household writ large” retained a continuing hold on popular imagination. The portrayal of political leaders and parties as feckless in managing public finances, as presiding over excessive public debt, and as in collusion with over-powerful bankers, invited electoral punishment. Evidence suggests that aligning oneself with debt reductionattracts broad public support. Despite neo-Keynesian macroeconomic insights, and modern consumer, financial, and promotional cultures, states still occupy a political world in which folk beliefs about debt retain a strong hold on how leaders behave. The more practical problem stems from the paradox that, although voters want action to tackle debt in the aggregate, few are ready to accept the ensuing consequences.

MORALITY AND DEBT

How far, and in what ways, is debt “bad”? What is the appropriate behavior of both creditors and debtors? What is the proper balance between, on the one hand, systemic stability and collective solidarity and, on the other, avoidance of moral hazard in managing sovereign debt? Who are the innocent victims and who, in the interests of fairness, should bear the fiscal pain of macroeconomic adjustment? How far should institutional feasibility define and, if necessary, restrict responsibility?

At the heart of many of these questions is the way in which creditor-debtor relations form a dyad. There cannot be creditors without debtors, any more than “surplus” states without “deficit” states in trade. In short, although their relationship is unequal, creditors need debtors. Moral ambiguity—and the absence of easy political solutions—originates from the problem of balancing the claims of creditors to superior virtue and uniqueness with those of debtors for recognition and honor. It can, in principle, be addressed by procedural rules that bridge different moral positions and overcome power differentials. In their absence, there is high risk of grievance, harassment, despair, and victimhood.

Credible commitment to such procedural rules depends on creditors’ recognition that adjustments cannot be made by debtors alone. The political difficulties lie in how to get each to face up to the implications of the mutual, asymmetric dependence of creditor and debtor states. Their relationship has features of a prisoners’ dilemma, in which neither side can defect without causing serious damage to the other. Managing this dilemma is easier when the institutional conditions are in place to help sustain an evolutionary, stable pattern of conditional cooperation. As with the euro area, a set of rules of the game that encourage repeated interactioninduce cooperation. However, risks remain. Creditor-state elites retain a paramount interest in limiting their liability. Moreover, one, or both parties, faced with deeply unpalatable choices, may choose to pursue a game of chicken, in which the bluff of the other is called. And, miscalculation can have high costs for all.

The politics of creditor–debtor relations are exacerbated by a moralizing language of “saints” and “sinners,” which is laced with feelings of pride in national virtue, on the one side, and of shame, humiliation, and resentment, on the other. Esoteric technical vocabulary and efforts to construct inclusive processes of debate and negotiation cannot hide the extent to which the idea of sovereign creditworthiness is a world of identities and symbolism, to which powerful, historically grounded, and often idiosyncratic feelings are attached.

Qualitative advancement in thinking about creditor-debtor relations and sovereign creditworthiness thus depends on strengthening their ethical dimension and promoting cultural change in two ways.

First, analysis of sovereign creditworthiness needs to move beyond a narrow, utilitarian, and financial view of balance sheets. It must also examine outcomes from longer-term and society-wide perspectives. This more expansive view involves taking account of wider expectations with respect to governance, social welfare, and environmental quality. A critical reexamination of sovereign creditworthiness reveals ethical questions about the operation and power of financial markets, including the net social value of financial innovations like derivatives and securitization.

Deep analysis suggests changes in the functioning of financial markets, including credit rating agencies, to reduce conflicts of interest, increase transparency, and avert excessive risk-taking through financial instruments of questionable net social value. One option is to rely on improvements in internal governance within financial markets. Examples include changes within credit rating agencies and greater accountability of managers for long-run performance, notably by changes to bank bonus practices. However, Turkeys do not vote for Thanksgiving, to paraphrase the British saying. External pressure from supervisors and regulators is required.

Secondly, there need to be corrections to the political short-sightedness that so often bedevils—and raises the costs—of debt crises. Political leaders of creditor states have great difficulties in persuading their domestic political elites and publics to make short-term sacrifices as taxpayers for long-term gains from avoidance of debt default and the systemic risks that follow. This problem is greater when it involves rescuing states, such as Greece and Cyprus, that are judged to be plagued by endemic corruption and failing governance capacity.

Within the euro area, the German federal government hesitated over the Greek bailout for some four months from January-February 2010, till after key elections. The German media was littered with images of lazy, corrupt, and featherbedded Greeks, enjoying pensions much earlier than Germans. They portrayed a bloated, privileged Greek public sector of unknown dimensions. These images ignored the reckless lending by German and other EU banks to Greece. In the end, German hesitation contributed to higher final costs of the eurozone-IMF bailout in May 2010. Political leadership is a tough call when it seeks to reframe moral arguments in terms that more judiciously apportion blame. As the Greek crisis gathered momentum in 2011–12, German political leadership instead resorted to dramatization of the existential threat to the eurozone and the European Union in order to overcome the deep reluctance of elite and public opinion to shoulder the costs of further financial assistance.

Better management of sovereign debt crises, though, goes to the heart of the functioning of liberal democracies. Current practices highlight the risks of disconnection between, on the one hand, domestic political competition and electoral choices and, on the other, policies to restore sovereign creditworthiness that are negotiated or imposed internationally. Disconnection is revealed in the growth of popular alienation from conventional forms of politics. In this context, space opens for populist political mobilization against external diktat, benefitting far Left and far Right parties. This phenomenon was apparent in the electoral performance of the National Front in the French Presidential and Assembly elections of 2012, of Syriza in the two Greek elections of 2012, and of the Five-Star Movement in the Italian elections of 2013.

THE RECKLESS, THE FECKLESS, AND THE INNOCENT

Creditors are prone to be seen as “saints,” debtors as “sinners.” Virtue is attached to the former (prudence, hard work), and vice to the latter (fecklessness, laziness). This kind of language puts at stake dignity, honor, and mutual respect. It arouses base as well as noble emotions, including resentment, grievance, and rage. The moral and emotional dimensions of debt are intimately intertwined.

To be effective, those managing sovereign debt crises have to be acutely sensitive to this powerful psychological dimension. Otherwise, those on the receiving end of punitive adjustments will mobilize to express their outrage. Building credibility in sovereign bond markets became mainstream in macroeconomic theory after the 1970s: What mattered for sovereign creditworthiness was management of market expectations, a key element of which was financial market psychology. States had to restore their credibility by increases in taxation, reductions in public-sector employment and wages, and benefit cuts. They had to align themselves with the technocratic nostrums of unelected bodies: central banks, international financial institutions, and financial market lobbies.

However, credibility in this narrow sense is only part of a much bigger and more complex political story about how states best sustain their reputation and power. The politics of sovereign creditworthiness is about the capacity to distinguish the legal contract governing creditor–debtor relations from the wider social contract on which governance is supposed to rest. The indicators of loss of creditor confidence are higher interest rates on debt. The indicators of loss of public confidence are social protest, electoral gains for extremist parties, and the drift of centrist parties toward the embrace of extremist positions.

Talking about creditors and debtors without implicit judgments about moral worth is very difficult—but it is time to do so.

Link.

Viaje a la libertad económica

Animado por una entrevista de dos amigos liberales, Gabriel Colominas y Álex Bové, el domingo leo Viaje a la libertad de Daniel Lacalle. Digo lo de “animado gracias a” porque desde el inicio de la crisis el número de libros sobre la crisis ha aumentado vertiginosamente sin que a este aumento haya venido acompañado de la correspondiente calidad. En efecto, estamos inundados de datos e información, pero andamos muy parcos en conocimiento y ya no digamos criterio económico para evaluar los temas.

Para poder tomar decisiones en la vida, de cualquier tipo, hacen falta básicamente dos cosas: información, que obtenemos a través del estudio y la lectura; y criterio, que vamos adquiriendo con la experiencia y la praxis. El libro que reseño está escrito por una persona informada y con criterio, de ahí mi recomendación.

El libro presenta, si digo viaje personal del autor quizás será demasiado, pero si me parece correcto hablar de testimonio personal del autor en su viaje intelectual y de crecimiento personal en el que, a través de diferentes episodios, se conduce a la conclusión que articula todo el relato: por qué el gasto esclaviza y la austeridad libera. En suma, el libro constituye un potente alegato en defensa de los mercados y como estos –contrariamente  a lo que en todavía amplios círculos sociales se cree – éstos son indispensables para construir sociedades justas y prósperas y, muy especialmente, para que esta justicia y prosperidad llegue a los más débiles y desamparados.

Este alegato, como decía, no sigue la estructura clásica de ningún manual de economía o de libro de texto sino que fluye de manera muy ágil y dinámica en breves capítulos –hasta un total de treinta y cinco– en donde se pone en tela de juicio diversos temas de actualidad que abarcan desde la presente crisis y las políticas para sacarnos de ésta hasta el debate en torno la energía. En cada uno de estos capítulos el autor cita las obras que le han ayudado a llegar a estas conclusiones, pone ejemplos y, en definitiva, comparte con el lector su experiencia vital haciéndole partícipe del que ha sido su crecimiento profesional e intelectual. Todo lo anterior se realiza a través de una prosa sencilla, ágil y efectiva.

Además, realiza este viaje con las alforjas llenas. Le dice don Quijote a Maese Pedro: “El que lee mucho y anda mucho, ve mucho y sabe mucho”. Lacalle es un autor leído y viajado. Es por eso, que uno de los factores que explican el éxito del libro de Lacalle es la existencia de un importante capital previo por parte del autor, en forma de bagaje familiar (del que el autor da algunas pinceladas muy interesantes), académico y laboral, y que se pone al servicio de la historia y de los argumentos que se quieren transmitir al futuro lector. Esta doble visión académica y profesional es lo que le da al libro un plus adicional con respecto a otras obras del género.

La argumentación general que nos ofrece el libro tiene un anclaje en el liberalismo clásico que mejor se sintetiza en las obras clásicas de Mises y Hayek. Este sólido anclaje que transmite el autor es lo que permite luego ser transversal y permeable a la hora de realizar este particular viaje y a lo largo de sus más de 380 páginas desfilan autores de diferentes corrientes y pensadores, clásicos y modernos, de aquí y de fuera, que ayudan al lector inexperto adquirir un marco de referencia en donde se mueve el pensamiento económico (desde todos sus ámbitos: desde el más filosófico al más financiero) en nuestros. Así, por el libro de Lacalle desfilan desde el bueno de Julian Simon hasta Aristóteles, pasando por Keynes/Hayek o algunos de los economistas más influyentes hoy en día en el ámbito mundial (para bien y para mal) como Krugman, Stiglitz, Acemoglu, Rogoff o Taleb, entre otras muchas otras referencias en las que se incluye la de buenos amigos como la profesora María Blanco y el profesor Juan Ramón Rallo.

El viaje ofrece al lector el marco de referencia básico (añado actual) de lo son los fundamentos del liberalismo y el armazón teórico necesario para interpretar la compleja y difícil coyuntura económica y social en la que nos encontramos y que, como dicta la lógica más elemental, sino somos capaces de establecer un diagnóstico dar con las políticas adecuadas es imposible.

Postscriptum

El libro solo tiene un fallo. Más que fallo es una apreciación personal de quién firma esta crítica. El autor introduce la “curva de Laffer” pero su representación no resulta del todo precisa. La llamada “curva de Laffer” es una simplificación teórica realizada en la década de los años 70s y popularizada durante la presidencia Reagan, por la cual se señala la existencia de un óptimo en la relación entre tipo impositivo (presión fiscal) y la recaudación obtenida por parte del Estado. De esta manera, y de forma ciertamente intuitiva, se observa como en entornos en donde la presión fiscal es muy elevada, por ejemplo España actualmente (pero se puede generalizar al conjunto de los países desarrollados), una bajada en los gravámenes fiscales se traduce en mayores ingresos fiscales, no menos, debido al efecto positivo que tiene el liberar carga fiscal sobre el tejido productivo. En suma, existen más y potentes incentivos al trabajo y al ahorro lo que se traduce en mayor actividad económica y, a la postre, también en una mayor recaudación.

Arthur Laffer dibujo esta relación en forma de “seno” (ver www.laffercenter.com) y no de “U” invertida, como aparece en el libro de Lacalle, para enfatizar el hecho de que esta relación no se puede medir mediante ninguna función. De esta manera Laffer, al expresar su relación en una curva paralela al eje de las ordenadas (Y), evitaba confusiones con un último toque de genialidad que, además, entronca con el papel que se le da a las matemáticas dentro del debate metodológico que se dio entorno a finales del siglo XIX entre la escuela Histórica y la Austriaca (pero eso ya eso otro artículo).